~Proceedings ICMCISMCI2014 14-20 September 2014, Athens, Greece those theorists who rely on conventional methods to bring about consistent, or in any case, proven analytical results tend to incorporate alternative visualizations that need not be condoned by the composer or geared toward performance. As Denis Smalley explains, there possibly exist for an electroacoustic work "three types of score which might contain perceptually relevant information": (1) a score used by a performer in mixed works of live electronic music, (2) a "technical" score, or a record of how the piece was produced, and (3) a "diffusion score," "often a free, sketchy, graphic representation of the sounding context," which would be useful as an indication of timing for engineers and composers diffusing the work in a concert. "But," Smalley is quick to warn, outside of these three variations, "we must be cautious about putting too much faith in written representations" [3:108]. And I extend this caution also to other forms of visualization in the context of music analysis. Though visual representations are tempting, they are lacking for several reasons. First, images that display the entirety of a composition, such as a spectrogram, do not adequately convey the experience of music in time. Secondly, as observed by Mary Simoni [5] (for alternative examples, see also [6]), time-domain representations, even those which compile in "realtime"-depicting frequency and amplitude as they unfold-do not adequately convey timbral qualities, and merely communicate, as with any analysis, only that which the analyst intuits as relevant. From this, it is surmisable that a third analytical framework, focusing explicitly on the firsthand experience of music as it unfolds in time, could bypass these secondary visualizations. In this paper, I would like to focus on this third analytical strategy, and to propose a timebased analysis of electroacoustic music absent visualization. Fish & Fowl (2011) by Juliana Hodkinson and Niels R nsholdt is an electroacoustic work rife for suggestive inferences. Coupled with clicking heels and cracking whips, the sexualized breathing of the female "protagonist" in Fish & Fowl is an allusion to a territory typically, if tacitly, forbidden in scholarly rapport. Stripping the character of her moaning, whipping, and pleasurable exclamations, a spectrogram realization of Fish & Fowl would barely turn heads, leaving behind only a residue of strong and weak impulses. In the visual realm, absent these timbral qualities, the semantic meaning-though conveyed easily through audible utterances-is all but lost. If music analysis is to be reconceived to include the many semantic inferences listeners experience synchronically in the midst of hearing, we analysts must find a new method of exploration, one that departs from a dependence on visual representations. Music theorist Brian Hulse's [7] musical engagement with the "virtual," which he frames within a Deleuzian reading of Bergson's philosophy, proposes a musical 1 This critique of phenomenological invocations in music theory has recently been revisited by Maryam A. Moshaver [4]. hearing that acknowledges ambiguity and engages in the pluralism of many possible aesthetic experiences. As Hulse explains, "In the virtual, we find a technical approach to thinking musical time whereby the rich temporal depths of music, completely obscured by traditional notation (which collapses time to an all-atonce spatial representation), become accessible to a different kind of thought; a thought that is fully in contact with music as a process rather than as a static product" [7:50]. Taking to task Hulse's invitation toward a Deleuzian "thinking music," this paper is organized in three parts. I first outline the three perspectives of the "virtual" through the synthesis as conceived in Deleuze's framing of time through the experience of difference and repetition. Second, I then tie these perspectives to musical experience by way of Hodkinson and R nsholdt's Fish & Fowl. And lastly, in attempts to convey a theoretical framework for electroacoustic music while also maintaining an openended interpretation, I then raise questions about the manner in which listeners can potentially derive meaning from music with erotic overtones without essentializing or reducing the analysis to so-called representative assumptions about the plot, subject, source, essence, nature, or labor of this music and the musicians involved in its creation and production. 2. TIME AS THE SYNTHESIS OF DIFFERENCE AND REPETITION "The primacy of identity, however conceived," writes Gilles Deleuze, "defines the world of representation" [8: xix]. For Deleuze, "identity" is always linked to a foundation, a ground, or in other words, a hierarchical construction of the "concept." This stilted, atemporal concept comes to be a representation of the thing, an infinite and unmovable truth. The flaw of representation then arises from the myth that our perception of time and indeed of life itself-is constituted as a sequence of discrete events. As determined by Deleuze, the atemporal invocation of the "concept" is a central fallacy in Hegel's philosophy. Hegel's abstraction of concepts gives a false sense of objectivity; the concept arises independently, is unchanging, and remains frozen in time-long after even Hegel has passed. In Deleuze's words, "Hegel substitutes the abstract relation of the particular to the concept of the general for the true relation of the singular and the universal in the Idea. He thus remains in the reflected element of 'representation"' [8:10]. Recognizing Deleuze's reformulation of the "concept" as a temporally bound object, in her generous reading, philosopher and feminist theorist Elizabeth Grosz [9] explains that concepts, for Deleuze, "emerge long before the human emerges... Concepts have a date; they have a history." Breaking with the Enlightenment tradition "that wants to link concepts to the development of reason," Grosz incites Deleuze's notion of "Chaos" as "the real outside representation." In the chaos of the "real," prior to the rational imposition of logic, a concept is constantly moving and - 149 -
Top of page Top of page