Add to bookbag
Title: Political liberty
Original Title: Liberté politique
Volume and Page: Vol. 9 (1765), p. 472
Author: Louis, chevalier de Jaucourt (biography)
Translator: Thomas Zemanek [University of Michigan]
Subject terms:
Political law
Original Version (ARTFL): Link
Rights/Permissions:

This text is protected by copyright and may be linked to without seeking permission. Please see http://quod.lib.umich.edu/d/did/terms.html for information on reproduction.

URL: http://hdl.handle.net/2027/spo.did2222.0001.247
Citation (MLA): Jaucourt, Louis, chevalier de. "Political liberty." The Encyclopedia of Diderot & d'Alembert Collaborative Translation Project. Translated by Thomas Zemanek. Ann Arbor: Michigan Publishing, University of Michigan Library, 2009. Web. [fill in today's date in the form 18 Apr. 2009 and remove square brackets]. <http://hdl.handle.net/2027/spo.did2222.0001.247>. Trans. of "Liberté politique," Encyclopédie ou Dictionnaire raisonné des sciences, des arts et des métiers, vol. 9. Paris, 1765.
Citation (Chicago): Jaucourt, Louis, chevalier de. "Political liberty." The Encyclopedia of Diderot & d'Alembert Collaborative Translation Project. Translated by Thomas Zemanek. Ann Arbor: Michigan Publishing, University of Michigan Library, 2009. http://hdl.handle.net/2027/spo.did2222.0001.247 (accessed [fill in today's date in the form April 18, 2009 and remove square brackets]). Originally published as "Liberté politique," Encyclopédie ou Dictionnaire raisonné des sciences, des arts et des métiers, 9:472 (Paris, 1765).

Political Liberty, the political liberty of a state is shaped by fundamental laws which establish therein the distribution of the legislative power, the executive power in matters of public law, and the executive power in matters of civil law, so that these three powers are all linked to one another.

The political liberty of a citizen is that tranquility of the mind which arises from the belief that each person has in his security, and for one to have this security, the government must be such that one citizen does not fear another. Good civil law and policy assure this liberty ; it triumphs even more when criminal law determines punishment based on the nature of the crime.

There is in the world a nation that has political liberty as its expressed purpose in its constitution; and if the principles upon which it is founded are solid, its advantages must therein be recognized. On that note, I recall having heard someone tell a true genius from England that Corneille had better illustrated the height of feelings which inspire political liberty than any English poets, in this discourse given by Viriate to Sertorius. [1]

Set free the Tagus, and forget the Tiber.
Freedom is naught when all the world is free.
‘Tis sweet to have it and see all men groan
Beneath the yoke and in their chains make moan.
‘Tis sweet to show one’s freedom to the eyes
Of those enslaved along the Rhone or captive
In Rome, and see envied by humbled peoples
That deep respect which is the valiant’s portion. [2]

Sertorius, act. IV. sc. vi.

It is not my intent to pronounce that the English currently enjoy the prerogative of which I speak; I am satisfied to agree with M. de Montesquieu, that it is established by their laws, and that after all, this extreme political liberty should not mortify those who have only a moderate amount of it, because the excess of reason is not always desirable, and generally men almost always thrive better in the mean rather than extremes.

1. Pierre Corneille’s tragedy Sertorius was was first performed in Paris in February 1662. Calendrier électronique des spectacles sous l’ancien régime et sous la révolution, “Sertorius,” (accessed September 15, 2009).

2. Corneille, Pierre, Moot Plays of Corneille, trans. Lacy Lockert (Nashville: Venderbilt University Press, 1959), 233.