A Dictionary of Greek and Roman biography and mythology. By various writers. Ed. by William Smith. Illustrated by numerous engravings on wood.

340 ARISTOTELES. Mathematics, therefore, stand half-way between physics and metaphysics. (Met. i. 6, p. 20, 23, i. 9, p. 33, 23, xi. 1. p. 212, 22.) Mathematical existence exists only 3vvaiLs (according to potentiality) in the abstractive operation of the understanding, and is therefore no independent existence, nothing substantial. We arrive at the cognition of its peculiar definitions not from the idea, but only by means of separation (e. g. auxiliary lines in figures for proof). On that account, neither motion nor the idea of purpose occurs in mathematics. (Met. iv. 2, Phys. ii. 9.) In this science, that which is simple, as an abstractum, forms the starting-point, and its necessity depends on our advancing from the simple to the composite, or from the basis to that which is based upon it. (Phys. ii. 9.) Respecting the axioms from which the mathematical sciences proceed, mathematics can therefore say nothing (Met. iv. 3), because these belong to every existing thing as such.-* Respecting the view taken by Aristotle of the mathematical sciences, see Biese, ii. pp. 225-234. B. THE PRACTICAL SCIENCES. Mathematics, restricted as the science is to the quantitative, can exhibit the good and the beautiful only as they manifest themselves in that immutability which consists in the fixed order and harmony of the quantitative. But the way in which these two, the good and the beautiful, acquire existence in the department of the mind, is considered and pointed out by the practical sciences, Ethics, Politics (with Oeconomics as an appendix), and Poetics (Aesthetics, Philosophy of Art). 1. Ethics. 1. General Definitions.t-The highest and last purpose of all action, according to Aristotle, is happiness (satiastovia. Eth. Nic. i. 2-7, x. 6-8, and elsewhere). This he defines to be the energy (ievp-yTa) of life existing for its own sake (perfect life), according to virtue existing by and for itself (perfect virtue). As the highest good, it must be pursued for its own sake; as the highest human good, its essence must be derived from the peculiar destination of man. Accordingly, happiness is the activity of the soul in accordance with virtue during a separate independent period of existence. (Eth. Nie. i. 7.) The two principal component parts of this definition are virtue, and external S The only mathematical work of Aristotle (pjaOrivarnTiKLv, Diog. Laert. v. 24) quoted by ancient writers is lost. The method which was followed at a later time for mathematics, rests altogether on the doctrine of proof given in the Analytics. Aristotle probably composed no separate treatises on arithmetic and geometry. In his Organon he frequently borrows examples from geometry. Aristotle, as an opponent of the Pythagoreans, laid great stress on the separation of arithmetic and geometry. (Anal. post. i. 27, Met. v. 6.) + In this review of the ethical system of Aristotle we follow of course the progress of the Nicomachean Ethics, as being the principal work. The first two books contain the general part of ethics, the remaining eight books carry out the definitions of this portion more closely. ARISTOTELES. good circumstances as means of virtue. Virtues are of two kinds, either intellectual virtues (iLavo',ruiai), or moral virtues (7'itcal), according to the distinction between the reasoning faculty, and that in the soul which obeys the reason. According to this distinction, the origin of the virtues, which Aristotle points out in the second book of the Ethics, is also different. The intellectual virtues may be learnt and taught, the ethical virtues are acquired by practice. In the case of these, therefore, we must have regard to the practice of them in particular cases; therefore, only quite general directions admit of being given respecting them. Youth must be accustomed and trained "to rejoice and be sorry in the proper way," for grief and joy are the criteria of virtue, inasmuch as it is the proper medium between excess and deficiency. (Eth. Nic. ii. 2.) To be able to refrain from sensual desires with pleasure is to be temperate. The intemperate man experiences pain at such abstinence, when he is compelled to practise it. By the practice of virtue the man becomes good himself; and virtue is therefore a habit, and that too accompanied by fore-choice (Zis lrpoaimp)rn/), which keeps the medium in our subjective inclinations and impulses (Elh. Nic. ii. 6), and keeps the medium in that way in which the rational man ( (ppviuos) determines. This medium assumes different forms according to the several impulses, under the influence of which the actor has reference either solely to himself, or to others also. The medium is opposed to the extremes; they contradict each other, and the proper measure or degree depends on the particular inclinations of the individual. 2. Special part. - Virtue is based upon free, self-conscious action. Aristotle, therefore, before developing the several virtues specially, defines the idea of responsibility (iii. 1-7), and then and not before gives the development of the ethical (iii. 8, v. extr.) and logical (vi.) virtues. As now, in the definition of happiness, virtues and the means of virtue formed the chief parts, so the second section of the special part of ethics is devoted to the internal and external circumstances of life, which become the means of virtue through the good manifesting itself in them as the purpose. Continuance in a course of virtue is connected chiefly with firmness of character, which exhibits itself as well in abstinence (4yKpdTreia) which resists pleasure, as in endurance (icaupepia, a Platonic idea: see Plat. Laches), which remains unshaken, even by the attacks of pain. (Eth. Nic. vii. 1-12.) This firmness therefore manifests itself especially in the manner in which a man demeans himself towards pleasure and pain. This leads to the investigation of the essential nature of pleasure and pain. (Eth. Nic. vii. 12, &c.) Farther, in the social life of men, friendship, which is itself a virtue (viii. 1), and indeed the crown of all virtues, is a principal means for a steady continuance in virtue. Aristotle, therefore, in the 8th and 9th books, treats of friendship with the most careful explicitness. He shews that it forms the foundation for all kinds of unions, and contributes to the realization of the good in the smaller and larger circles of social life. Lastly, the unrestricted exercise of each species of activity directed towards the good is accompanied by the feeling of an undisturbed energy. and this harmony, in which the external and the internal are in accordance, pro

/ 1113
Pages

Actions

file_download Download Options Download this page PDF - Pages 336-340 Image - Page 340 Plain Text - Page 340

About this Item

Title
A Dictionary of Greek and Roman biography and mythology. By various writers. Ed. by William Smith. Illustrated by numerous engravings on wood.
Author
Smith, William, Sir, ed. 1813-1893.
Canvas
Page 340
Publication
Boston,: Little, Brown and co.,
1867.
Subject terms
Classical dictionaries
Biography -- Dictionaries.
Greece -- Biography.
Rome -- Biography.

Technical Details

Link to this Item
https://name.umdl.umich.edu/acl3129.0001.001
Link to this scan
https://quod.lib.umich.edu/m/moa/acl3129.0001.001/355

Rights and Permissions

These pages may be freely searched and displayed. Permission must be received for subsequent distribution in print or electronically. Please go to http://www.umdl.umich.edu/ for more information.

Manifest
https://quod.lib.umich.edu/cgi/t/text/api/manifest/moa:acl3129.0001.001

Cite this Item

Full citation
"A Dictionary of Greek and Roman biography and mythology. By various writers. Ed. by William Smith. Illustrated by numerous engravings on wood." In the digital collection Making of America Books. https://name.umdl.umich.edu/acl3129.0001.001. University of Michigan Library Digital Collections. Accessed June 16, 2025.
Do you have questions about this content? Need to report a problem? Please contact us.