A Dictionary of Greek and Roman biography and mythology. By various writers. Ed. by William Smith. Illustrated by numerous engravings on wood.

ARISTOTELES. 1. There is a science which considers existe as such, and the definitions pertaining to ii such. 2. It is not the same with any one of particular sciences, for all these consider onl part of what exists and its attributes. 3. ' principles and highest causes of things must hai nature appropriate only to them. Existence is indeed defined in various ways, denotes at one time the What and the idea, another time the condition or constitution, ma tude, &c., of a thing; of all the definitions, h ever, the What, which denotes the substance the first. (Miet. vii. 1. p. 1028, Bekk.) All o definitions only state attributes or qualities of first definition, and are not in their nature i: pendent, or capable of being separated from substance. On the other hand, the idea of stance (ovrioa) lies at the foundation of our ide; everything, and we do not arrive at the cogni of anything when we know how great, or wlb &c., it is, but when we know wChat it is. question, therefore, is, What is the substas (ris ri oo-ria;) which has ever been the ol of philosophical investigation. (Met. vii. 1 1028.) Aristotle distinguishes three kindE substances: 1. Substance perceptible by the se (Met. xii. 1, 2, vii. 7), which is finite and rishable, like single sensible objects. The menta of this sensible substance are, - a. matter, that which is fundamental, constant particular things, the negative in relation to other; e. the motive principle, the pure fort elJos. 2. The second higher kind of substant that which may be perceived by the senses, b imperishable, such as the heavenly bodies. I the active principle (ivepyeia, actus) steps which, in so far as it contains that which is t produced, is understanding (voils). That whi contains is the purpose, which is realized by mn of the Eivpyeta. The two extremes are here tentiality and agency (matter and thought). passive universal and the active universal. two are not subject to change. That whi( changed is the particular thing, and passes one into the other by means of something else which it is moved. The purpose, in so far is the motive principle, is called the cause (dp but, in so far as it is the purpose, it is the rec alrtia. (Met. v. 1, 2.) The active principle reality to that which it contains in itself: thiE mains the same: it is still, however, matter, w is different from the active principle, though are combined. That which combines them is form, the union of both. The relation of newly coined idea of 4vrEiXeXea, or the pui realized by the formative principle, to the id EPepyeia, is this: ITEAEXELta signifies in the ferent grades of existence the completion whi in conformity with each single existing tt and Evipyeia denotes the actuality which conformity with this completion. (Metaph. i p. 179. 8, Brand.) Thus the soul is essenl eirTAeXeia.* ARISTOTELES. 337 3. The third kind of substance is that in which Livagfus, evipyeia, and iserXeXsia are united; the absolute substance; the eternal, unmoved; but which is at the same time motive, is pure activity (actus purus, Met. xii. 6, ix. 8, xii. 7), is God himself. This substance is without matter, and so also is not a magnitude. The chief momentum in the Aristotelian philosophy is, that thought and the subject of thought are one; that what is objective and thought (the EiVep'ya) are one and the same. God himself is eternal thought, and his thought is operation, life, action,-it is the thought of thought.- Objects exist in their truth only in so far as they are the subjects of thought, are thoughts. That is their essence (oaiara). In nature, indeed, the idea exists not as a thought, but as a body; it has, however, a soul, and this is its idea. In saying this, Aristotle stands upon the highest point of speculation: God, as a living God, is the universe. In the course of the investigation, Aristotle, with careful regard to, and examination of, the views of earlier philosophers, points out that neither abstractly universal, nor particular, sensuously perceptible essences can be looked upon as principles of existence. Neither the universal apart from the particular, nor the particular by itself, can be a principle of the natural and spiritual world; but the absolute principle is God,-the highest reason, the object of whose thought is himself. Thus the dominion of the Anaxagorean vovs was declared in a profounder manner by Aristotle. In the divine thought, existence is at the same time implied. Thought is the sum and substance of the universe, and realizes itself in the eternal immutable formative principles which, as the essences indwelling (imman'ent) in the material, fashion themselves so as to assume an individual existence. In man, the thought of the divine reason completes itself so as to become the self-conscious activity of thinking reason. By it he recognizes in the objective world his own nature again, and so attains to the cognition of truth. With these slight intimations, we must here leave the subject. VIII. THE PARTiCULAR SCIENCES. Respecting the Essence of the Particular Sciences, and the division of them into Theoretical and Practical Sciences.-The science of the particular can thing, the potentiality must pass into actuality. The principle of the transition from the potential to the actual in a thing Aristotle calls entelecheia (ro iEvreXAs h'xov), because it unites both the potentiality and the actuality. Every union of potentiality and actuality is a motion, and accordingly the entelecheia is the principle of motion ( " 'roi avvdset OVros ETVEI'rXeXeC1a 7010 oTOV, Kivitsoo-ri). The potentiality (s'vagis) can never become actuality (icvoyeia) without entelecheia; but the entelecheia also cannot dispense with the potentiality. If the entelecheia does not manifest itself in a thing, it is merely a thing Ka'rca SlVayiv; if it does manifest itself, it becomes a thing Icar' ie'ipyemav. The same thing is often both together, the former in reference to qualities which it has not yet, but can obtain; the latter in reference to attributes already actually present in it. (Buhle, in Erschs and Gruber's Encyclopaidie.) * Met. xii. p. 1074, Bekk., asrdy d'pa vooe eifirep i-rl To Kpar'ri y r alTov o-r <'ny ) vdfscr-s, vo('-rews ei;<r tS. 7 vives -- * The actuality of each thing presupposes an original internal potentiality, which is in itself only conceivable, not perceptible. The potentiality of a thing is followed by its actuality in reference either to mere existence or to action. This actuality is ivpyeta, anctus, and is perceptible. Riut, that the potential thing may become a real

/ 1113
Pages

Actions

file_download Download Options Download this page PDF - Pages 336-340 Image - Page 337 Plain Text - Page 337

About this Item

Title
A Dictionary of Greek and Roman biography and mythology. By various writers. Ed. by William Smith. Illustrated by numerous engravings on wood.
Author
Smith, William, Sir, ed. 1813-1893.
Canvas
Page 337
Publication
Boston,: Little, Brown and co.,
1867.
Subject terms
Classical dictionaries
Biography -- Dictionaries.
Greece -- Biography.
Rome -- Biography.

Technical Details

Link to this Item
https://name.umdl.umich.edu/acl3129.0001.001
Link to this scan
https://quod.lib.umich.edu/m/moa/acl3129.0001.001/352

Rights and Permissions

These pages may be freely searched and displayed. Permission must be received for subsequent distribution in print or electronically. Please go to http://www.umdl.umich.edu/ for more information.

Manifest
https://quod.lib.umich.edu/cgi/t/text/api/manifest/moa:acl3129.0001.001

Cite this Item

Full citation
"A Dictionary of Greek and Roman biography and mythology. By various writers. Ed. by William Smith. Illustrated by numerous engravings on wood." In the digital collection Making of America Books. https://name.umdl.umich.edu/acl3129.0001.001. University of Michigan Library Digital Collections. Accessed June 18, 2025.
Do you have questions about this content? Need to report a problem? Please contact us.