Elements of the philosophy of the human mind. By Dugald Stewart. Rev. and abridged, with critical and explanatory notes, for the use of colleges and schools. By Francis Bowen ...

REASONING AND DEDUCTIVE EVIDENCE. 460 the essential distinction between its literal and its mefcaplhorical acceptations, he might have at once cleared up the mystery. After telling us that "1laws, in their most extensive signification, are the necessary relations (les rapports nizcessaires) which arise from the nature of things, and that, in this sense, all beings have their laws; —that the Deity has his laws; the material world its laws; intelligences superior to man their laws; the brutes their laws; man his laws;" he proceeds to remark, " That the moral world is far from being so well governed as the material; for the former, although it has its laws, which are invariable, does not observe these laws so constantly as the latter." It is evident that this remark derives whatever plausibility it possesses from a play upon words; from confounding moral laws with physical; or, in plainer terms, from confounding laws which are addressed by a legislator to intelligent beings, with those general conclusions concerlning the established order of the universe, to which, when legitimately inferred from an induction sufficiently extensive, philosophers have metaphorically applied the title of Laws of N-ature. In the one case, the conformity of the law with the nature of things does not at all depend on its being observed or not, but on the reasonableness and moral obligation of the law. In the other case, the very definition of the word laiw supposes that it applies universally; insomuch that, if it failed in one single instance, it would cease to be a law. It is, therefore, a mere quibble to say, that the laws of the material world are better observed than those of the moral; the meaning of the word law, in the two cases to which it is here applied, being so totally different, as to render the comparison or contrast, in the statement of which it is involved, altogether illusory and sophistical. Indeed, nothing more is necessary to strip the proposition of every semblance of plausibility, but an attention to this verbal ambiguity. This metaphorical employment of the word law, to express a general fact, although it does not appear to have been adopted in the technical phraseology of ancient philosophy, is not unusual among the classical writers, when speaking of those phys.

/ 508
Pages

Actions

file_download Download Options Download this page PDF - Pages 462-466 Image - Page 465 Plain Text - Page 465

About this Item

Title
Elements of the philosophy of the human mind. By Dugald Stewart. Rev. and abridged, with critical and explanatory notes, for the use of colleges and schools. By Francis Bowen ...
Author
Stewart, Dugald, 1753-1828.
Canvas
Page 465
Publication
Boston: J. Munroe & co.,
1859.
Subject terms
Psychology

Technical Details

Link to this Item
https://name.umdl.umich.edu/aje6414.0001.001
Link to this scan
https://quod.lib.umich.edu/m/moa/aje6414.0001.001/479

Rights and Permissions

These pages may be freely searched and displayed. Permission must be received for subsequent distribution in print or electronically. Please go to http://www.umdl.umich.edu/ for more information.

Manifest
https://quod.lib.umich.edu/cgi/t/text/api/manifest/moa:aje6414.0001.001

Cite this Item

Full citation
"Elements of the philosophy of the human mind. By Dugald Stewart. Rev. and abridged, with critical and explanatory notes, for the use of colleges and schools. By Francis Bowen ..." In the digital collection Making of America Books. https://name.umdl.umich.edu/aje6414.0001.001. University of Michigan Library Digital Collections. Accessed May 1, 2025.
Do you have questions about this content? Need to report a problem? Please contact us.