Knowledge, Foundations, and Discourse: Philosophical Support for Service-Learning Typically, these lines are drawn between discourses in which commensuration is possible and those in which it is not. That is, we view science as "hard" or objective in its methodology and epistemic criteria because there exists some common ground-empirical observation, for example-for adjudicating knowledge claims. On the other hand, we conceive of politics, art, and literature as fields that lack an independent ground for resolving disagreement, fields in which points of view cannot achieve the status of genuine cognition but remain simply matters of taste or opinion. The distinction, we believe, is one that separates inquiry into what is "out there" from inquiry into what we "make up,"4 and it is in virtue of the indeterminate ontological status of the subject matter that we cast a suspicious eye toward the latter. Pragmatism argues that the line between commensurable and incommensurable discourses does not reveal deep distinctions between where certain knowledge is possible and where it is not. The key premise of the pragmatic view is that the line between different discourses is contingent not necessary, and that it has not been and will not be drawn in the same place throughout the course of intellectual history. Rorty (1979) recasts the substance of this distinction between discourses by generalizing Kuhn's distinction between normal and revolutionary science into a distinction between normal and abnormal discourse: [N]ormal discourse is that which is conducted within an agreed-upon set ofconventions about what counts as a relevant contribution, what counts as answering a question, what counts as having a good argument for that answer or a good criticism of it. Abnormal discourse is what happens when someone joins in the discourse who is ignorant of these conventions or who sets them aside. [T]he product of normal discourse [is] the sort of statement which can be agreed to be true by all participants whom the other participants count as "rational." The product of abnormal discourse can be anything from nonsense to intellectual revolution...(p. 320) On this conception, commensuration in a given discourse does not precede the discourse itself. Instead, it is a by-product of agreed-upon practices of inquiry that have continued long enough for shared conventions, rules, and standards of evidence to develop and come into plain view. It is an indication that the discourse and its norms are useful, productive, or effective in the context in which it occurs. It is not a revelation of something deep about the underlying structure of knowledge, for neither commensuration nor incommensuration are permanent or necessary features of any discourse. In certain periods, it may be as easy to determine the aesthetic merit of a painting as it is to determine the scientific validity ofa measurement, while in other periods, "it may be as difficult to know which scientists are actually offering reasonable explanations as it is to know which painters are destined for immortality" (Rorty, 1979, p. 322). Thus, the line between commensurability and incommensurability is nothing more than the line between normal and abnormal discourses. And this latter distinction does not parallel the distinctions between "hard" and "soft," objective and subjective, finding and making, nature and spirit, or facts and values.' Natural science and other fields of inquiry do not necessarily line up as normal and abnormal discourses, respectively, although they may at particular slices in time. Both modes of discourse occur within science as well as non-science, and on a long view of intellectual history, we will find that the patterns of argumentation and justification in the natural sciences do not differ qualitatively from the types of discourse in the humanities and social sciences. The point of distinguishing between normal and abnormal discourses is not to prioritize one or the other as a better way of knowing. It would be ineffective if not impossible to teach, to learn, or to conduct a program of research without rules, conventions, shared vocabularies, and other means of systematizing inquiry. Normal discourse allows us to apply foundational reasoning when it is useful to do so. In a sense, it is the starting point for intellectual activity, for abnormal discourse is possible and meaningful only when it occurs with a consciousness of how it departs from a wellunderstood norm. Abnormal discourse always presents itself as an alternative (e.g., to tradition, to a dominant view). As a consequence, it "is always parasitic upon normal discourse" (Rorty, 1979, pp. 365-366). Nevertheless, because normal discourses are the products of substantial intellectual and material investments, perhaps we need a more forceful reminder that "normal participation in normal discourse is merely one project, one way of being in the world" (Rorty, 1979, p. 365). Instead of "reducing all possible views to one" through some means of universal commensuration (p. 11
Top of page Top of page