A tract on duelling: wherein the opinions of some of the most celebrated writers on crown law are examined and corrected ... in order to ascertain the due distinction between manslaughter and murder. By Granville Sharp.

About this Item

Title
A tract on duelling: wherein the opinions of some of the most celebrated writers on crown law are examined and corrected ... in order to ascertain the due distinction between manslaughter and murder. By Granville Sharp.
Author
Sharp, Granville, 1735-1813.
Publication
London :: (first printed in 1773) Second edition with additions printed for B. White and Son; and C. Dilly,
1790.
Rights/Permissions

To the extent possible under law, the Text Creation Partnership has waived all copyright and related or neighboring rights to this keyboarded and encoded edition of the work described above, according to the terms of the CC0 1.0 Public Domain Dedication (http://creativecommons.org/publicdomain/zero/1.0/). This waiver does not extend to any page images or other supplementary files associated with this work, which may be protected by copyright or other license restrictions. Please go to http://www.lib.umich.edu/tcp/ecco/ for more information.

Link to this Item
http://name.umdl.umich.edu/004892691.0001.000
Cite this Item
"A tract on duelling: wherein the opinions of some of the most celebrated writers on crown law are examined and corrected ... in order to ascertain the due distinction between manslaughter and murder. By Granville Sharp." In the digital collection Eighteenth Century Collections Online. https://name.umdl.umich.edu/004892691.0001.000. University of Michigan Library Digital Collections. Accessed April 25, 2025.

Pages

Page [unnumbered]

A TRACT ON DUELLING.

NO MAN can give or accept a chal∣lenge to fight with weapons, and kill his antagonist (on any private difference whatever) without being guilty of Wil∣ful Murder, such as ought to be excluded from the benefit of clergy. For Wilful Murder is the killing of a man ex ma∣litiâ proecogitatâa 1.1; which malice is either implied or express,b 1.2 or, as judge Hale calls

Page 2

it, Malice in Law, or ex presumptione Legisc 1.3; and malice must necessarily be implied when a man wilfully strikes or wounds another with any offensive weapon whatever, because that is

an act that must apparently introduce harm
d 1.4, and the intention to do harm makes it murdere 1.5; so that the allowance which the writers of the two last centuries have made for sudden anger (without preserv∣ing a proper distinction of the case where∣in it really deserves consideration) is unjust in itself, as well as dangerous to society; for few men would entertain such absurd notions of honour, as to think themselves obliged to revenge affronts with their swords or pistols, if the risque of being hanged up as felons and murderers for their own gentleman∣like satisfaction, was rendered obvious by

Page 3

just and proper decisions of the Law on this point.

In every charge of murder, the fact of killing being first proved, all the cir∣cumstances of Accident, Necessity, or Infirmity are to be satisfactorily proved by the prisoner, unless they arise out of the evidence produced against him: for the law presumeth the fact to have been founded in malice, until the contrary appeareth.
Judge Foster, 255.

The cases of homicide which are justi∣fied or excused by the above-mentioned circumstances of Accident and Necessity, are well understood, and, by many emi∣nent writers, sufficiently explained un∣der the heads of Misfortune and Self-defence. But with respect to those cases of Homicide, which are attended with

Page 4

circumstances of infirmity (the third branch of circumstances mentioned above) the writers on crown law in general have been very indiscriminate, notwithstanding that the true distinction between Murder and Manslaughter de∣pends entirely on a clear stating of those cases of infirmity, which really deserve consideration and excuse.

Judge Foster, indeed, is, for the most part, nice and accurate in his distinctions; yet he has paid so great a regard to the authority of precedents, that he has been unwarily led away (as well as other writers) from the necessary conclusions of his own arguments upon this point; I shall, nevertheless, make use of his words as far as they express my own opinion of the subject.—

Whoever would shelter himself under the plea of Provocation must prove his case to the satisfaction of the jury. The

Page 5

presumption of law is against him, till that presumption is repelled by contrary evidence. What degree of Provocation, and under what circum∣stances heat of blood, the Furor bre∣vis, will or will not avail the De∣fendant is now to be considered.

Words of Reproach, how grievous soever, are not a Provocation suffi∣cient to free the Party killing from the guilt of murder. Nor are inde∣cent provoking actions or gestures expressive of contempt or reproach, without an assault upon the person.
(p. 290.) But I think myself obliged to add that even an assault* 1.6upon the person is NOT
a Provocation suffi∣cient to free the Party killing from the guilt of murder,
(though this

Page 6

learned judge seems to think otherwise. See Sect. iii. p. 295) unless all the cir∣cumstances which are necessary to ren∣der it excusable by the plea of self∣defence can clearly be proved. For if the Killing in a sudden fray is not ex necessitate, (as in Self-defence, or in the lawful Defence of others), it must be esteemed voluntary; and voluntary is the same thing as wilful; which neces∣sarily includes malice. For Bracton says,

Crimen non contrahitur nisi Voluntas nocendi intercedat & voluntas et pro∣positum distinguunt Maleficium,
&c.
The Guilt is not incurred unless the intention of injuring intervenes, for the Intention and Purpose (or design) marks the Felony (or malicious Deed.)
Lib. iii. c. 17. So that malice must necessarily be presumed, whenever the killing is not ex necessitate, especially if the fatal blow be wilfully given with a weapon; for in that case a man must

Page 7

necessarily be supposed to strike,

cunt occidendi animo,—with murderous in∣tent,
because the Voluntas nocendi is apparent; and, consequently, the malice, in such a case, is not only implied but clearly expressed; so that the sudden anger is only a further proof of the malice and "intention to do harm."

Bracton has accurately laid down the proper distinction to be observed in the plea of an excusable Necessity for killing.

Quo casu distinguendum est utrum Necessitas illa fuit evitabilis vel non. Si autem evitabilis, et evadere posset abs∣que occisione, tune erit reus homi∣cidii,
(and a felonious homicide or manslaughter, in the days of Bracton, had the same meaning that we now apply to Murder).
Si autem inevi∣tabilis, quia occidit hominem sine odii meditatione in metu & dolore

Page 8

animi, se et sua liberando cum aliter
(mortem propriam Fleta, lib. i. c. 23.)
evadere non posset, non tenetur ad poenam homicidii* 1.7.
Bract. lib. iii. c. 4. And Staunford remarks, that the necessity ought to be so great, that it ought to be esteemed inevitable, or otherwise it shall not be excused; so that the whole matter consists (says he) in the inevitable necessity, without which the killing is by no means excusablef 1.8 so

Page 9

that the learned Judge Foster certainly goes too far, when he insinuates, in the passage before cited,

that an assault upon the person
(without mentioning the necessary exception con∣cerning inevitable Necessity)
is a pro∣vocation sufficient to free the party killing from the guilt of murder.
For a farther distinction (besides that of inevitable necessity) is also to be ob∣served, which is very accurately laid down, even by judge Foster himself, in p. 291, though the same would be use∣less, if an assault upon the person was to be admitted as a sufficient provocation to the act of killing.
It ought to be remembered (says he) that in all other cases of homicide upon slight provocationg 1.9, if it may be reasonably

Page 10

collected from the weapon made use of, or from any other circumstance, that the Party intended to kill, or to do some great bodily harm, such Homi∣cide will be Murder. The mischief done is irreparable, and the outrage is considered as flowing rather from brutal rage or diabolical malignity, than from human frailty. And it is to human frailty, and to that alone, the Law indulgeth in every case of felonious Homicide.

The first instance which he gives by way of illustration to this doctrine is cited from Judge Hale, vol. i. p. 473.

If A. come into the wood of B. and pull his hedges, or cut his wood, and B. beat him, whereof he dies, this is manslaughter, because, though it was not lawful for A. to cut the wood, it was not lawful for B. to beat him, but either to bring him to a Justice

Page 11

of Peace, or punish him otherwise according to law.
But here Lord Hale is not sufficiently distinct in stating the case; because circumstances are wanting, which are necessary for the determination of such a case, whether it ought to be esteemed manslaughter or murder. The accurate Judge Foster was sensible of this want of necessary circumstances, and therefore adds,
But it must be understood (says he) that he beat him, not with a mischievous intention, but meerly to chastise him for the trespass, and to deter him from committing the like. For if he had knocked his brains out with a bill or hedgestake, or had given him an out∣rageous beating with an ordinary cud∣gel beyond the bounds of a sudden resentment, whereof he had died, It had been Murder. For these circum∣stances are some of the genuine symp∣toms of the Mala Mens, the heart

Page 12

bent upon mischief, which, as I have already shewn, enter into the true notion of Malice in the legal sense of the word.
P. 291.

The next instance he mentions is that of the parker tying the boy to his horse's tail. Which was (says he)

held to be murder.
For it was a deliberate act, and savoured of cruelty.
But the third instance, viz. that of Sted∣man the soldier killing a woman with a sword (which Judge Foster mentions as a case that was held clearly to be no more than manslaughter) was, most cer∣tainly, wilful murder: for tho' it appeared that the woman had struck the soldier on the face with an iron patten; yet she afterwards fled from him, and he
pur∣suing her, stabbed her in the back.

Now if such a case of wilful killing is to be esteemed only manslaughter, it

Page 13

entirely perverts the just arguments already quoted from the same author concerning the cases wherein human frailty deserves to be indulged! May I not use his own words against him? That "these circumstances" (the pur∣suing, and stabbing the woman in the back)

are some of the genuine symp∣toms of the mala mens, the heart bent upon mischief.
Whereas, if he had struck her merely with his fist, or with a small stick not likely to kill, and had unluckily, and against his intention, killed, it had been but manslaughter. For this is the necessary distinction for which I contend in all cases of killing where the striking (not the killing) is voluntary: and I cannot so well express my meaning as in the words of Judge Foster himself, though that sensible and acute reasoner is afterwards misled from the truth of his own doctrine, by

Page 14

paying too much regard (I mean an indiscriminate regard) to the practice of the Courts, which, in this point, has frequently been erroneous.

In page 290, after the 1st section (already quoted) concerning the cir∣cumstances, which

are not a provo∣cation sufficient to free the Party Killing from the Guilt of Murder,
he adds,
This rule will, I conceive (says he) govern every case where the Party Killing upon such provocation maketh use of a deadly weapon, or otherwise manifesteth an intention to kill, or to do some some great bodily harm. But if he had given the other a box on the ear, or had struck him with a stick or other weapon not likely to kill, and had unluckily and against his intention killed, it had been but manslaughter. The difference between the cases is plainly this. In the for∣mer,

Page 15

the malitia, the wicked vindictive disposition already mentioned, evidently appeareth: in the latter it is as evidently wanting. The Party, in the first trans∣port of his passion, intended to chas∣tise for a piece of insolence which few spirits can bear. In this case the benignity of the law interposeth in favour of human frailty; in the other its justice regardeth and punisheth the apparent malignity of the heart.
P. 290 and 291.

Nevertheless, the same author, in p. 296, endeavours to excuse killing in sudden rencounters, without preserving this necessary distinction concerning "the use of a deadly weapon," and

the intention to kill.

To what I have offered (says he) with regard to sudden rencounters, let me add, that the blood, already too

Page 16

much heated, kindleth afresh at every pass or blow. And in the tumult of the passions, in which meer instinct self-preservation, hath no inconsider∣able share, the voice of reason is not heard. And therefore the law, in condescension to the infirmities of flesh and blood, hath extenuated the of∣fence.
But the Law, in reality, makes no such condescension, though the Courts of Law have, indeed, indiscrimi∣nately done so, and have occasioned a mul∣titude of bad precedents, wherein wilful murder has been excused under the name of manslaughter; and this unhappy dif∣ference between the Law, and the cor∣rupt practice of the Courts, with respect to this point, has unwarily led the more modern writers on crown-law into con∣cessions, which are absolutely contra∣dictory to the just doctrines laid down in other parts of their excellent works.

Page 17

When I speak of such respectable and justly revered authors as Sir Edward Coke, Sir Matthew Hale, Lord Chief Justice Holt, &c. No person can conceive that I am misled by personal or party prejudice against their opini∣ons; and as I have, really, the highest esteem and veneration for their memory, not only as great and learned lawyers, but as true patriots, and, above all, as sincere Christians, and worthy honest men, I should not presume to contro∣vert any point that has been laid down by such excellent lawyers (so accomplished as above) was I not armed by their own authority; for no other authority is suf∣ficiently authentic for the purpose of correcting such deservedly esteemed wri∣ters; though I must acknowledge my obligation to the more ancient writers for the discovery of the errors of which I complain.

The proper distinction to be observed

Page 18

between murder and manslaughter is well laid down by Sir Matthew Hale. "Mur∣der" (says he)

being aggravated with malice presumed or implied, but man∣slaughter Not.
1 Hale's P. C. 466* 1.10.

This rule is good and unexceptiona∣ble; and therefore it must appear, that even Sir Matthew Hale himself is mis∣taken in the paragraph preceding this quotation, where he says that

Man∣slaughter, or simple homicide, is the vo∣luntary killing of another without ma∣lice express or implied:
for though there may be a voluntary striking with∣out malice, yet I hope I have already proved, that there cannot be a voluntary killing

Page 19

without malice express or implied, except in the legal execution of justice, and in the case of self-defence and its several branches, which some writers (rather improperly have, indeed, called voluntarya 1.11 though they proceed from an inevitable neces∣sityb 1.12 Nevertheless even the great Sir Edward Coke (and before him the learn∣ed Lambard in his Eirenarcha, p. 250.) was guilty of this same impropriety of expression. "Some manslaughters" (says Sir Edward Coke, 3 Inst. cap. viii. p. 55.)

be voluntary, and not of malice forethought, upon some sudden fall∣ing out. Delinquens per iram pro∣vocatus puniri debet mitiusc 1.13 And this for distinction sake (says he) is called manslaughter.
But it is a very indiscriminate distinction (if I may

Page 20

use such an expression concerning the writings of so great a man,) because the maxim "Delinquens per iram," &c. can only be admitted in case where the malice is neither express nor implied: for instance, when the Striking is volun∣tary; but the Killing, or Manslaughter, is involuntary, and unexpected; as when a man, in sudden anger, gives an un∣lucky blow merely with his fist, or with a small stick, or small stone,d 1.14 (meaning

Page 21

only to correct) which, undesignedly, oc∣casions death; for, in such cases, the

Page 22

malice is not implied; whereas, in a voluntary homicide, even a Malice pre∣pensed is implied, according to Sir Ed∣ward Coke's own definition of that term, viz. "That it is voluntary, and of set purpose, though it be done upon a

Sudden Occasion: for if it be Volun∣tary, the law implieth Malice,
3 Inst. c. xiii. p. 62.—Sir William Blackstone has also fallen into the same error in his 4th vol. chap. xiv. p. 191. where he in∣forms us that Manslaughter is
the un∣lawful killing of another, without malice either express or implied: which may be either voluntarily upon a sudden heat; or involuntarily, but in the

Page 23

commission of some unlawful act.
In both of which he is also mistaken; for, with respect to the latter, his doctrine cannot be admitted, except in cases where the circumstances of the unlaw∣ful act amount only to a bare trespasse 1.15

Page 24

For I propose, in the course of this tract, to mention several allowed cases, on

Page 25

good authority, wherein even the invo∣luntary or undesigned killing is not deem∣ed manslaughter, but murder, when the acts, which occasioned death, were un∣lawful: and, with the respect to the for∣mer, it is a manifest inconsistency, in all these great writers, to rank voluntary killing under the head of manslaughter, in the modern confined sense of that once general term; because a voluntary kill∣ing (except in the case of self-defence,

Page 26

through inevitable necessity, which some writers have, rather improperly, called voluntaryf 1.16) is certainly the same thing as a wilful killing; and either of them must be allowed to be the proper defi∣nition of what we now understand by the term Murder (though the meaning of that word was, originally, very dif∣ferent. See le Mirroir de justice, 1642, c. i. sect. xiii. p. 104. and Lambard's Eirenarcha, c. vii. p. 239.) because, in

a voluntary or wilful killing, malice is necessarily implied;
and, consequently, voluntary killing is excluded from the favour due to manslaughter by the rule

Page 27

which these learned writers themselves admit, viz.

that manslaughter is with∣out out malice express or implied;
so that they are really guilty of a contradiction in terms; because the malice, or inten∣tion of killing, is undeniable, if the killing be voluntaryg 1.17: and therefore, as it is a maxim that
Allegans contraria non est audiendus
(Jenk. Cent. fo. 16.) I am compelled to reject the definition of manslaughter given by these learned writers, as far as it is contradictory to to that excellent rule, already cited, for the distinction of manslaughter from murder, which they themselves admit, viz. that
manslaughter is without malice express or implied.

The errors, of which I complain, were not originally occasioned by these cele∣brated

Page 28

authors, but by a previous cor∣rupt practice in the courts, which had been introduced by degrees, and at last unhappily prevailed, through a false idea of mercy and consideration for sudden anger; and also through the want of preserving the proper distinction of cases, wherein manslaughter in sudden anger is really excusable. The proper distinction to be observed is, when the inten∣tion of killing is not necessarily impiled in the act itself; as when a man strikes ano∣ther merely with his hand, in sudden anger; or thrusts him suddenly from him, whereby he falls and receives a hurt, which occasions death; in these, and similar cases, the striking, or thrusting is, indeed, voluntary, yet the killing, or manslaughter, is not so, but entirely undesigned and unexpected; which proper and necessary distinction the Law Commentators have unhappily neglected. For, though the act of stri∣king

Page 29

or thrusting in anger bears some re∣semblance to malice, and though such an act is certainly unlawful in itself, yet it is reasonable to make some allow∣ance for the frailty of human nature, and the sudden passion of a man that is provoked, whenever a more criminal malice is not necessarily impiled in the act itself, which occasions death. And in this lenity we are justified by the laws of God, whereby such cases of manslaughter in sudden anger, as I have mentioned, were excused without any other penalty than that of banish∣ment to a city of refuge.

If he thrusth 1.18 him suddenly〈 in non-Latin alphabet 〉〈 in non-Latin alphabet 〉without

Page 30

enmityi 1.19 (〈 in non-Latin alphabet 〉〈 in non-Latin alphabet 〉 Numb. xxxv. 22.) —the congregation shall restore him to the city of his refuge, &c.
v. 25.) Yet the very same action, if done in ha∣tred, (〈 in non-Latin alphabet 〉〈 in non-Latin alphabet 〉 see the 20th verse) and even a blow with the hand in enmity, (〈 in non-Latin alphabet 〉〈 in non-Latin alphabet 〉 see the 21st verse, apparently meaning, when there was an express proof of ma∣lice, or intention to kill,) were to be deemed unpardonable; "he shall surely die."

But, it is remarkable, that these are the only two cases wherein an express proof of malice was required; for in all the examples given in the same chapter of killing with a weapon, or with a stone wherewith a man may die, (meaning such a stone as from its shape or size might be deemed a sufficient weapon to occa∣sion death) there is not the least men∣tion

Page 31

made of malice (〈 in non-Latin alphabet 〉〈 in non-Latin alphabet 〉 Hatred, or 〈 in non-Latin alphabet 〉〈 in non-Latin alphabet 〉 Enmity) which is a sufficient proof that the same were necessarily implied from the stroke, when given with a weapon; for, in that case, the com∣mand was peremptory.

If he smite him with an instrument of iron, so that he die,
he is a murderer (〈 in non-Latin alphabet 〉〈 in non-Latin alphabet 〉 Retsch, or Killer, perhaps from thence the Eng∣lish word wretch) "the murdererk 1.20
shall

Page 32

surely be put to death:
(v. 16.) the same also, if he smote him with
a stone wherewith he may die,) or with an hand weapon of wood.
But in none of these cases is there the least mention of malice; which was, therefore, most certainly implied: and the congregation (to which our trials per Pares are in some degree similar) were to judge

Page 33

"according to these judgments;" see 24th verse. For the slayer was not to die, un∣til he stood before the congregation in judgment; see 12th verse: and then, if it did not appear, that the killing was at unawares (〈 in non-Latin alphabet 〉〈 in non-Latin alphabet 〉 in error) see 11th verse, or, as the same meaning is ex∣pressed in different words in Deut. xix. 4. 〈 in non-Latin alphabet 〉〈 in non-Latin alphabet 〉 ignorantly, or without know∣ledge (agreeable to the example, there laid down, for all other cases of mere misfortunel 1.21) the malice was presumed

Page 34

from the weapon with which the stroke was made; for the hatred〈 in non-Latin alphabet 〉〈 in non-Latin alphabet 〉 and en∣mity

Page 35

〈 in non-Latin alphabet 〉〈 in non-Latin alphabet 〉 were never enquired after in any cases where a wilful stroke was given with "an instrument of iron," or

a weapon of wood,
or even with "a stone (wherewith a man may die)" that is, if it were such a stone as was appa∣rently capable of occasioning the death of a man (see Numb. xxxv. 16. to 19.) all which crimes were unpardonable by the law of God; "he shall surely die."

And the Levitical Law is, certainly, in this point, still binding, even under the dispensation of the gospel; because the reason and justice of it still subsists, as in other moral laws.

So that the allowance usually made for sudden anger, when the blow is given with a weapon, is so far from deserving the name of "a proper distinction in the crime of killing," (as some contend) that

Page 36

it is apparently founded in a want of that proper distinction, which the laws of God and reason require, concerning cases of manslaughter, wherein sudden anger is really excusable; which can only be when the killing is not voluntary, or, at least, the intention of killing not apparent; as in the cases before-menti∣oned of a man striking another merely with his hand,m 1.22 or fist, in sudden anger; or the sudden thrustingn 1.23 a man down,

Page 37

by which he is hurt in falling, so that death unexpectedly ensues. In these and similar cases the malice or the inten∣tion of killing is not necessarily implied in the action itself; and, therefore, if all the other circumstances are also free from premeditated malice and laying in wait, the law has reserved a reasonable use of an unreasonable popish indulgence, called The Benefit of Clergy, to relieve the undesigning manslayer (if the occasion

Page 38

was not unlawful) from the too great severity of the common law; for in such cases we may safely admit Sir Ed∣ward Coke's maxim,

Delinquens per iram provocatus puniri debet mitius,
3 Inst. 55.o 1.24

But a false idea of mercy, and consi∣deration for sudden anger unhappily pre∣vailing in the Courts, this lenity was indiscriminately extended even to cases where the prepensed malice was necessa∣rily implied by the stroke; so that the wretch, who stabbed his neighbour in brutal anger, escaped with impunity, to the scandal of public justice. The bad effects of this false mercy, and injustice, became so notorious in the reign of King James I. that the legislature was obliged to seek a remedy; and a statute was then made (1 Jac. I. c. 8.) by which the

Page 39

benefit of clergy was taken away from

the offence of mortally stabbing an∣other, though done upon sudden provo∣cation.
Judge Blackstone's Com. b. 4. c. xiv. p. 193. But unfortunately this remedy proved almost as indiscrimi∣nate as the abuse intended to be correct∣ed by it; for it takes no notice of any other crime than that of stabbing; as if sudden anger was not equally criminal, when a man is killed "by throwing a hammer or other weapon;" or by
a shot with a pistol.
Ibid. p. 194. Whereas, in truth, no new law was wanted: nothing but a better admini∣stration of the old laws before-menti∣oned; for, in all such furious sallies of sudden anger, the malice was necessarily implied, or presumed, from the weapon, as well in the laws of God (which I have already shewn) as in the law of nations: —"Ex telo praesumitur malum consilium (says the learned Grotius)
nisi contra∣rium

Page 40

appareat.
p 1.25 And in his second book, de Jure Belli & Pacis, he remarks, "that either iron, a club, or a stone, comes under the denomination of a weapon.
Teli autem nomine ferrum, fustis, & lapis venit,
c. i. p. 175.

The reason of the severity in the di∣vine law, against striking with a weapon, is well expressed by Dr. Wells in his paraphrase on Numbers xxxv. 16 to 19.

Forasmuch (says he) as though he might have no malice to him before∣hand, yet his striking him with a sword, or hatchet, &c. shews he had an intention to do him mischief;
and, as another writer remarks
though per∣haps he had no formed intention to kill the person; yet he ought to have mo∣derated his passion, and could not be

Page 41

ignorant that such an instrument was capable of inflicting a deadly wound,

And, therefore, when a man is killed with a weapon (except it be by misfor∣tune, or in self-defenceq 1.26, when the Slayer could retire no further to save himself without striking; or else in such law∣ful and reasonable cases, wherein a man is not obliged to give back; as in the case of a peace officerr 1.27 who is assaulted

Page 42

in his duty; or when any other man en∣deavours to keep the peaces 1.28 or to save ano∣ther person from violence and oppressiont 1.29;

Page 43

or a womanu 1.30 in the necessary defence of chastity; or when any person resists the

Page 44

attack of a Robberw 1.31) I say, excepting these, and similar cases, if a man wil∣fully

Page 45

strikes another with a weapon in sudden anger, the design of killing is, by

Page 46

"the weapon, rendered express, as I have before observed, though the

prepensed malice
may, perhaps, more properly (upon a sudden provocation) be said to be implied; and it, certainly, is implied or presumed in law, though the sudden anger was but a moment before the fa∣tal strokex 1.32; so that, if no proof can be

Page 47

produced by the prisoner, of an inevita∣ble necessity, as in se defendendo, the act must, in reason and justice, be deemed "wilful murder of malice prepensed," such as was sufficiently excluded from the benefit of clergy by two express acts of parliament (23 Hen. VIII.c. i. and 1 Edw. VI.c.xii.) previous to the undistinguishing act of James I. against stabbing.

By an act of the 2 Edw. III. it was ordained that a charter of pardon

shall not be granted, but only where the

Page 48

king may do it by his oathy 1.33 that is to say, where a man slayeth another

Page 49

in his own defence, or by misfortune.
Now with respect to the first case, viz.

Page 50

"in his own defence," (or se defendendo) "all writers, both antient and modern,

Page 51

agree, that the killing of a man must

Page 52

bez 1.34inevitable, and that the manstayer must be able to prove, that he retired; and that he was obliged, ex necessitate, to strike, in order to save his own life; a plea which cannot be admitted in fa∣vour of a Man, who has accepted a challenge; or who has drawn his sword, in sudden anger, merely to revenge an affront.

Page 53

And with respect to the second par∣donable case, mentioned in the said act of Edw. III. viz. by Misfortune, I must ob∣serve, that there are some cases of ho∣micide that may even be said to happen by misfortune, or without intention, which are, nevertheless, deemed Murder. And the severity of the law, in this respect, will enable me, by comparison, to point out, more clearly, the absurdity and in∣justice of excusing homicide, in consi∣deration of sudden anger, when the mor∣tal stroke is given with a weapon in rencounters.

The cases of Misfortune or Accident, which are deemed Murder, are those wherein the act, which undesignedly occasions death, is in itself unlawfulaa 1.35.

Page 54

If the act be unlawful (says Lord Coke) it is murder. As if A. meaning to steal a deer in the park of B. shooteth at the deer, and by the glance of the arrow killeth a boy that is hidden in a bush; this is murder, for that the act was unlawful, although A. had no intent to hurt the boy, nor knew not of him.
3 Inst. 56. Lord Chief Justice Holt, indeed, says it is but manslaughter; in which he is mistakenbb 1.36. (See his Edition of Kelyng. Rex versus Plummer, 117.) But whether this be deemed murder or manslaughter, the killing is merely accidental, or by mis∣fortune; and, therefore, is certainly a much less crime than that of aiming at,

Page 55

and striking a man with a weapon, or shooting at him in sudden anger, howso∣ever great the previous affront may have been. For, in the former case, though the shooting at a deer belonging to an∣other person is both unlawful, and vo∣luntary, yet the manslaughter, which it accidentally occasions, is involuntary, and without intention; whereas in the vo∣luntary aiming, and shooting at a man, the act itself is not only unlawful, but implies malice; or rather, I may say, the malice is expressed by the act; and the sudden anger is so far from being an ex∣cuse, that it is, absolutely, a further proof of the malice and intention of killing. The malice was also implied in the case of the Lord Dacres, though his Lordship was not half so criminal in his unlawful hunting, as the passionate man who strikes with a weapon. See how the case is mentioned by Lord Chief Justice Kelyng, (Rep. p. 87. published by Judge Holt.)

Page 56

The Lord Dacres and Mansell, and others in his company came unlawfully to hunt in a forestcc 1.37, and being resisted, one of the company, when the Lord Dacres was a great way off, and not present, killed a man; judged murder in him and all the rest, and the Lord Dacres was hanged.

Lord Chief Justice Holt supposes a case in his Rep. of Rex versus Plummer, p. 117. in the same book, which is in some degree similar.

So (says he) if

Page 57

two men have a design to steal a hen, and the one shoots at the hen for that purpose, and a man be killed, it is murder in both, because the design was felonious.
See also the last para∣graph of p. 56.3 Inst. concerning the shooting at a tame fowl, of which this case, supposed by Judge Holt, is an ex∣planation. But surely the design must be much more felonious when a man wilfully strikes his neighbour with a weapon in sudden anger; because this must neces∣sarily be allowed to be an act
com∣mitted felleo animo, with a fell, furi∣ous, and mischievous mind and intent,
which is Lambard's definition of felony, c. vii. p. 224.

The implication of malice in the owner of a beast that kills a man, after warn∣ing given, will also further illustrate what has been said; for though mere carelessness or inconsideration might oc∣casion

Page 58

his neglect, so that the accident may, in some degree, be esteemed a misfortune, yet the law implies malice;

for if one keep a mastiff dog (says Sir James Astry, in his charge to grand juries, p. 18.) that is used to bite peo∣ple near the common highway; or bull or beast, that hath hurt any one (after notice) they kill any one, that will be murder in the Owner, although not present when the fact was done; and yet in this, and the other precedent cases, here is no express malice to be proved, but what the law construes to be so:
this is agreeable to the doc∣trine of Judge Staunford, P. C. lib. i. cap. 9.
Que si home ad un jument que est accustomé male faire et le Owner ceo bien sachant, negliga luy, eins suffra d'aller a large, et puis le jument tua un home: que ceo est felo∣nie in le owner, eo que, per tiel suf∣ferance: le owner semble d'aver volunté

Page 59

a tuer.
See also Crompton, p. 24. b. and 1 Hawkins, c. xxxi. § 8. And, according to Bracton, the Common Law imputes the death of a man by a beast, to any man, who follows, or drives the beast at the time of the misfortune;—
vel dum insequitur quis equum vel bovem, et aliquis a bove vel equo per∣cussus fuerit, et hujusmodi hoc imputa∣tur ei.
Bract. lib iii. c. iv. p. 120. b. If this law were still enforced, we should not have such continual complaints of accidents in the streets, by cattle, that are enraged, and made mad, through the cruelty of the two-legged brutes who drive them. For the first step that ought to be taken, in such cases, is, to seize the drivers; and, nineteen times out of twenty, it will be found, that the poor beast will recover it-self (when they are gone) from the excess of fear and rage which the Brutality of the hurrying

Page 60

Driversdd 1.38 had occasioned; so that it is plain where the guilt is to be imputed: but yet even a brutal driver is not so base and detestable as the man who wilfully strikes with a weapon in sudden anger. And again, he who aims to strike or shoot at a man, and accidentally kills a different person (whom perhaps he did not see) contrary to his intention (or by misfortune as it were) is, nevertheless, deemed guilty of wilful murder, though he had not the least anger, or resentment, against the person killedee 1.39. But surely the

Page 61

man who actually kills the person he aims at, in his anger, is at least as culpable! so that if sudden anger deserves no lenity in the former case, it certainly deserves none in the latter. Several cases also are mentioned by Sir William Blackstone, wherein sudden anger is not excusable, even though the death may be said to be "by misfortune," as there was no real intention of killing, yet rendered by the circumstances

equivalent to a deliberate act of slaughter.
See Comment. b. iv. chap. xiv. p. 199 and 200.
Also if even upon a sudden provocation (says he) one beats another in a cruel and unusual manner, so that he dies, though he did not intend his death, yet he is guilty of murder by an express malice;

Page 62

that is, by an express evil design, the genuine sense of malitia. As when a park-keeper tied a boy that was steal∣ing wood, to a horse's tail, and drag∣ged him along the park; when a master corrected his servant with an iron bar, and a schoolmaster stamped on his scholar's belly; so that each of the sufferers died; these were justly held to be murders, because the cor∣rection being excessive, and such as could not proceed but from a bad heart, it was equivalent to a deliberate act of slaughter.
But is not an express evil design as apparent, in the act of stri∣king a man with a weapon, in anger, (be the anger ever so sudden) as it is in these cases where death was not really intended? For surely the design of killing, is by the weapon rendered expressff 1.40; |which equally

Page 63

fulfils "the genuine sense of malitia," tho' perhaps, the prepensed malice may, more properly (upon a sudden provocation as above) be said to be implied than express. But whether it be express or implied, it undoubtedly constitutes murder; for malice is the leading circumstance which distinguishes manslaughter from murder, and therefore an express evil design, such as is apparent in the voluntary killing of a man, cannot be admitted under the head of simple homicide or manslaughter, because the necessary difference is want∣ing in the degree of the offence according to the excellent rule before cited from

Page 64

Sir Matthew Hale, viz.—

murder being aggravated with malice presumed or implied; but manslaughter not, &c.
1 Hale, P. C. 466.

I may probably seem guilty of much tautology in this little Work; but hope my Readers will excuse it, in considera∣tion of the necessity I am under, of re∣peatedly comparing the crimes of stri∣king with a weapon in sudden Anger, and of voluntary Killing, with so many other different cases, wherein even involuntary and accidental Killing have been solemnly adjudged Murder: and I apprehend that the severity of the Law, in the last∣mentioned cases, must sufficiently de∣monstrate such a general abhorrence in our Law to the shedding of Human Blood, that we cannot reasonably sup∣pose the same Law capable of admitting an excuse for voluntary Manslaughter on

Page 65

any private difference, howsoever great the provocation. Nevertheless, Mr. Hawkins ventures to assert a very dif∣ferent doctrine in his Pleas of the Crown, 1 Book c. xxviii. § 24.

I see no reason (says he) why a person, who without provocation is assaulted by another in any place whatsoever, in such a manner as plainly shews an in∣tent to murder him, as by discharg∣ing a Pistol, or pushing at him with a drawn Sword, &c. may not justify Killing such an Assailant, as much as if he had attempted to rob him: for is not he, who attempts to Murder me (says he) more injurious than he who barely attempts to rob me? And can it be more justifiable to fight for my goods than for my life? And it is not only highly agreeable to reason, that a man in such circumstances may lawfully Kill another, but it seems

Page 66

also to be confirmed by the general Te∣nor of our Law-books,
&c.

But howsoever specious this argument may appear, I hope I have already proved "by the general Tenor of our Law-books;" that the Justifiable Kill∣ing of a Man must be through an inevita∣ble necessity: and therefore what Mr. Hawkins afterwards advances, in his comparison of such a case with Homi∣cide in se Defendendo, cannot in the least justify either his opinion on that point, or his assertion concerning

the general Tenor of the Law-books.

He endeavours to represent the Volun∣tary Killing of a Man as Justifiable Ho∣micide, and consequently he must sup∣pose it a less crime than Excusable Ho∣micide, in se Defendendo.

He founds his opinion in the suppo∣sition of "some precedent Quarrel" in

Page 67

the latter, "in which" (says he)

both parties always are, or at least may justly be supposed to have been, in some fault, so that the necessity, to which a Man is at length reduced to kill another, is in some measure presumed to be owing to himself:
&c.

But may it not, as "justly be supposed" that the person, who Kills without such necessity, is also "in some fault?" Is not the Presumption of Law against him (as I have elsewhere shewn) by the bloody FACT, when he cannot prove that he endeavoured, at least, to retreat, in or∣der to avoid unnecessary bloodshed? And is not FACT a more substantial ground for a criminal charge, than any idea that a Court can possibly form con∣cerning the Murderous Intentions, which the Killer may attribute to the person Killed?

Page 68

The single circumstance that the Killer was under no necessity of endea∣vouring to retreat, and avoid the assail∣ant, is not only a proof that his own in∣tentions (though he might not be the first aggressor) were nearly as criminal, as those he attributes to the person Killed, but it also affords a strong presumption, that the latter was not very strenuous or sanguine, either in his attack, or in his supposed intention to commit murder: so that the very pretence, by which Mr. Hawkins endeavours to justify such a voluntary Killing, must necessa∣rily fall to the ground, whenever the Killer is unable to prove, that he endea∣voured to avoid the attackgg 1.41 And tho' the Deceased might have had

a Wea∣pon Drawn,
yet that circumstance affords no positive proof of his criminal

Page 69

intention; for he might have thought himself obliged to draw in his own de∣fence, through a reciprocal suspicion of his adversary's criminal intentions: and as he cannot plead his own cause, it is reasonable that the Law should pre∣sume, that he really did draw in his own defence, especially as the circumstance, that the Killer was under no necessity of endeavouring to avoid him, affords a sufficient Ground for such a presump∣tion:

And even in cases where it may be supposed that the person Killed might really have had "an intent to murder," we ought to remember that the Laws of England do not punish men merely for their "criminal intentions" without some fact! and, therefore, it would be highly absurd to suppose, that the Law, with∣out some apparent necessity, would en∣trust every individual, indiscriminately,

Page 70

with a supreme Authority, which it de∣nies even to the Highest and most solemn Courts of Justice; I mean an Authority to inflict capital punishment without a previous Trial per pares; and that mere∣ly for "a Criminal Intention;" which, in many cases, might as easily, (through fear, passion, or violent prejudice) be mistaken, or imaginary, as be real!

And therefore

an Assault upon the Person
is not (as I have before in∣sisted in p. 5. against the opinion of Judge Foster)
Provocation sufficient to free the Party Killing from the Guilt of Murder.

The case of Gentlemen in the Army, nevertheless, seems peculiarly hard upon such unhappy occasions. The first prin∣ciple of their profession is Courage; and the World, in general, is too de∣praved to distinguish in what cases a

Page 71

Man of true Courage may retreat with honour from the Assault of an Enemy; so that Military Men are liable to be unjustly despised, whenever they act rea∣sonably in cases either of insult, or as∣sault!

Yet, at the same time, it ought to be remembered, that those men who sub∣mit to the Slavish Yoke of other Men's depraved opinions or unreasonable cus∣toms (in contradiction to that natural Knowledge of Good and Evil, which they inherit, in common with the rest of Mankind, from our first Parents), can∣not justly be deemed Men of Honour; and, consequently, are unworthy of Rank in the honourable Profession of Arms. And though such men may support an outward appearance of Cour∣age in the eye of the world, by daring to violate the Laws of God and Man in private Quarrels, yet that very act af∣fords

Page 72

the most manifest token of the Want of real and steady Courage: for unless the submission to that depraved custom can be attributed to inconsidera∣tion, or to the want of Knowledge, it must necessarily be supposed, that the Duellist had not sufficient Courage to as∣sert his natural Right of Acting agreea∣ble to the Dictates of his own reason and conscience; and was unable to face the Terrors of an adverse Fortune in a good Cause; and therefore, like a wretched Coward, he yielded himself a prisoner and slave to the fashionable Depravity!

I am far from meaning however to charge all Soldiers with Cowardice that have fought Duels: sometimes Passion and false Pride, but more frequently in∣consideration, and ignorance of the Laws of God and Man (as I have before hint∣ed) occasion the base submission and conformity to those false and unreasona∣ble

Page 73

notions of Honour, which almost uni∣versally prevail.

Nor do I so much blame the Military Gentlemen, for this unnatural depravity, as I do the Professors of the Law; who ought to have set them a better exam∣ple, and yet, have rather contributed to the ignorance of the times, by the many gross perversions of our Law, which they have admitted into the Books. Gen∣tlemen of the Army are not obliged, in∣deed, to acquire a critical knowledge of the Law, but they must not forget that they are Men, as well as Soldiers; and that if they do not maintain the Natural Privilege of Men, (viz. that of thinking for themselves, and acting agreeable to the Dictates of their own Conscience, as Members of the Commu∣nity), they are unfit for British Soldiers, of whom the Law requires an acknow∣ledgement of her supremacy.

Page 74

For the Law will not excuse an un∣lawful Act by a Soldier, even though he commits it by the express Command of the highest military Authority in the Kingdom: and much less is the Sol∣dier obliged to conform himself impli∣citly to the mere opinions and false No∣tions of Honour, which his Superiors may have unfortunately adopted.—Even in publick military Service, or warlike Expeditions by National authority, the Law manifestly requires the Soldier to think for himself; and to consider, be∣fore he acts in any war, whether the same be just; for, if it be otherwise, the Common Law of this Kingdom will impute to him the Guilt of Murder.

And though the Law does not actually punish such general Crimes, as may un∣fortunately have obtained, at any time, the Sanction of Government, yet the time will certainly come, when all such

Page 75

temporizing military Murderers must be responsible for the innocent blood that is shed in an unjust War, if they have rendered themselves accessaries to it by an implicit, and, therefore, criminal obe∣dience to the promoters of it.

Item fit Homicidium in Bello,
(says the learned Bracton)
et tunc videndum utrum Bellum sit justum vel injustum. Si autem injustum, tenebitur occisor: si autem justum, sicut pro defensione patriae, non tenebitur, nisi hoc fecerit corrupta voluntate et intentionehh 1.42

Men of true honour, therefore, at the same time that they are sensible of their duty as Soldiers and Subjects to their King, must be mindful that they are subject also to the empire of reason, and are bound thereby, in common with all mankind, to maintain the dignity and natural freedom of Human Nature: and

Page 76

those Soldiers, who, in addition to their natural reason, have a true sense of Reli∣gion, will not only be mindful, that they are Soldiers and Subjects to an earthly King, but that they are also Soldiers and Subjects to the King of Kings; whose Laws and precepts they will, on all occasions, prefer to every other Com∣mand; and will obey the same with such a steady courage, as may be equal to every adversity, and undeserved suffering that threatens them.ii 1.43

Page 77

It was this indispensible, this happy disposition, and sense of superior duty, which prevailed even in an unlawful standing Army, that had been raised, and was expressly designed for arbitrary purposes, and which, nevertheless, con∣trary to all expectation, exerted itself in saving this Kingdom, at the Glori∣ous Revolution, from the Political Slavery, which then threatened it, as well as from the more intolerable Tyranny of the Romish Religion.

The Soldier, therefore, who has not Courage enough to profess, on all occa∣sions,

Page 78

a strict obedience to the Laws of his Country, according to the dictates of his own reason and Conscience, in prefer∣ence to every command, and every other opinion whatever, is unworthy of the British military service; being qualified rather to be inlisted with the slavish Troops of absolute Monarchs; or to serve in the Black Banditti of the Emperor of Morocco!

But I must return once more to the opinions of the Professors of Law

it is saidkk 1.44 that if he who draws upon another in a sudden Quarrel, make no pass at him till his sword is drawn, and then fight with him, and Kill him, is guilty of Manslaughter only,
&c. 1 Hawkins Pleas of the Crown, c.xxxi. § 28. for which he quotes Kelynge 55.

Page 79

61. and 131: but the pretence for this indulgence is as frivolous as the Doctrine is false, viz, "because (says Mr. Haw∣kins)

that by neglecting the opportu∣nity of Killing the other before he was on his guard, and in a condition to defend himself, with like Hazard to both, he shewed that his intent was not so much to kill, as to combat with the other, in compliance with those common notions of Honour,
&c.—But is not "the intent to kill," or to do some bodily harm, and certainly, at least, the Risque of Killing, included in the intention "to Combat" with dangerous weapons? And is it Justice? Nay! is it common Sense to excuse a Notorious Crime, by the Plea of an intention to commit another Crime almost as bad?

I have already shewn, by fair com∣parison with a variety of cases, that the crime of wilfully striking or Combating

Page 80

with weapons in sudden Anger, is a much more unlawful act than many others, wherein even involuntary and accidental Homicide has been solemnly adjudged Murder, and has been generally admitted as such by the Sages of our Law in their Reports; and it will therefore be highly disgraceful to our Law, but more parti∣cularly (because deservedly) to the pro∣fessors of it, if they should still persist in the unreasonable and unjust practice of pu∣nishing lesser Crimes with more severity than the crying Sin of voluntary Man∣slaughter, which, as I have already proved in my preface, is absolutely un∣pardonable in this World, by the Laws of God!

Glory in the highest to GOD; And on Earth PEACE. Towards Men GOODWILL.

Notes

Do you have questions about this content? Need to report a problem? Please contact us.