A Dictionary of Greek and Roman biography and mythology. By various writers. Ed. by William Smith. Illustrated by numerous engravings on wood.

208 ANTISTHENES. two works entitled Cyrus, on Gorgias in his Archelaus and a most furious one on Plato in his Satho. (Athen. v. p. 220, b.) His style was pure and elegant, and Theopompus even said that Plato stole from him many of his thoughts. (Athen. xi. p. 508, c.) Cicero, however, calls him " homo acutus magis quam eruditus" (ad. Att. xii. 38), and it is impossible that his writings could have deserved any higher praise. He possessed considerable powers of wit and sarcasm, and was fond of playing upon words; saying, for instance, that he would rather fall among Kopdices than KoAdaces, for the one devour the dead, but the other the living; and that one of his pupils stood in need f/3sAraplov KawoIVs, Kac 'ypacpeiov KcaLoV (i. e. Kal vyo). Two declamations of his are preserved, named Ajax and Ulysses, which are purely rhetorical, and an epistle to Aristippus is attributed to him. His philosophical system was almost confined to ethics. In all that the wise man does, he said, he conforms to perfect virtue, and pleasure is not only unnecessary to man, but a positive evil. He is reported to have held pain and even infamy (dPoia) to be blessings, and that madness is preferable to pleasure, though Ritter thinks that some of these extravagances must have been advanced not as his own opinions, but those of the interlocutors in his dialogues. According to Schleiermacher (Anmerkungen Czu Phileb. S. 204), the passage in the Philebus (p. 44), which mentions the theory, that pleasure is a mere negation, and consists only in the absence of pain, refers to the opinions of Antisthenes; and the statement in Aristotle (Ethi. Nic. x. 1), that some persons considered pleasure wholly worthless (Kot e pav^ov) is certainly an allusion to the Cynical doctrine. It is, however, probable that he did not consider all pleasure worthless, but only that which results from the gratification of sensual or artificial desires, for we find him praising the pleasures which spring Eic "rTs yvxusys (Xen. Symp. iv. 41), and the enjoyments of a wisely chosen friendship. (Diog. Laert. vi. 11.) The summum bonum he placed in a life according to virtue,- virtue consisting in action, and being such, that when once obtained it is never lost, and exempts the wise man from the chance of error. That is, it is closely connected with reason, but to enable it to develop itself in action, and to be sufficient for happiness, it requires the aid of energy (2cwKparIucKT) iXs); so that we may represent him as teaching, that the summum bonum, idperT, is attainable by teaching (SsaKardv), and made up of <ppodv?7ois and louxus. But here he becomes involved in a vicious circle, for when asked what ()p6vpor's is, he could only call it an insight into the good, having before made the good to consist in ()ppO'r-qs. (Plat. Rep. vi. p. 505.) The negative character of his ethics, which are a mere denial of the Cyrenaic doctrine, is further shewn in his apophthegm, that the most necessary piece of knowledge is id oicacd darojLaO8v, while in his wish to isolate and withdraw the sage from all connexion with others, rendering him superior even to natural affection and the political institutions of his country, he really founds a system as purely selfish as that of Aristippus. The Physicus of Antisthenes contained a theory of the nature of the gods (Cic. de Nat. Deor. i. 13), in which he contended for the Unity of the Deity, and that man is unable to know him by ANTISTHENES. any sensible representation, since he is unlike any being on earth. (Clem. Alex. Strom. v. p. 601.) He probably held just views of providence, shewing the sufficiency of virtue for happiness by the fact, that outward events are regulated by God so as to benefit the wise. Such, at least, was the view of his pupil Diogenes of Sinope, and seems involved in his own statement, that all which belongs to others is truly the property of the wise man. Of his logic we hear that he held definitions to be impossible, since we can only say that every individual is what it is, and can give no more than a description of its qualities, e. g. that silver is like tin in colour. (Arist. lMet. viii. 3.) Thus he, of course, disbelieved the Platonic system of ideas, since each particular object of thought has its own separate essence. This also is in conformity with the practical and unscientific character of his doctrine, and its tendency to isolate noticed above. He never had many disciples, which annoyed him so much that he drove away those who did attend his teaching, except Diogenes, who remained with him till his death. His staff and wallet and mean clothing were only proofs of his vanity, which Socrates told him he saw through the holes o! his coat. The same quality appears in his contempt for the Athenian constitution and social in stitutions generally, resulting from his being him self debarred from exercising the rights of a citizec by the foreign extraction of his mother. His phi losophy was evidently thought worthless by Plati and Aristotle, to the former of whom he was per sonally hostile. His school is classed by Ritte among the imperfect Socraticists; after his deat] his disciples wandered further and further from a] scientific objects, and plunged more deeply int fanatical extravagances. Perhaps some of thei exaggerated statements have been attributed t their master. The fragments which remain of hi writings have been collected by Winckelman (Antisthenes, Fragmenta, Turici, 1842), and thi small work, with the account of him by Rittc (Gesch. der Phlilosophie, vii. 4) will supply all th information which can be desired. Most of th ancient authorities have been given in the cours of this article. We may add to them Arriai Epiclet. iii. 22, iv. 8, 11; Lucian, Cynic. iii. 541; Julian, Orat. vii. [G. E. L. C.] ANTI'STHENES ('AvKurTLo-'s), a disciple HERACLEITUS, wrote a commentary on the wor of his master. (Diog. Laert. ix. 15, vi. 19.) ' is not improbable that this Antisthenes may I the same as the one who wrote a work on tI succession of the Greek philosophers (at rd ihXo(r6dpwv 6raoxal), which is so often referred by Diogenes Laertius (i. 40, ii. 39, 98, vi. 77, 8 vii. 168, &c.), unless it appear preferable to assil it to the peripatetic philosopher mentioned I Phlegon. (de Mirabil. 3.) [L. S.] ANTI'STHENES ('A-ernOlems), of RHODI a Greek historian who lived about the year B. 200. He took an active part in the politic affairs of his country, and wrote a history of 1 own time, which, notwithstanding its partiali towards his native island, is spoken of in terms high praise by Polybius. (xvi. 14, &c.; con Diog. LaZrt. vi. 19.) Plutarch (de Fluv. 22) mc tions an Antisthenes who wrote a work call Meleagris, of which the third book is quoted; a Pliny (H. N. xxxvi. 12) speaks of a person of t same name, who wrote on the pyramids; I

/ 1113
Pages

Actions

file_download Download Options Download this page PDF - Pages 206-210 Image - Page 208 Plain Text - Page 208

About this Item

Title
A Dictionary of Greek and Roman biography and mythology. By various writers. Ed. by William Smith. Illustrated by numerous engravings on wood.
Author
Smith, William, Sir, ed. 1813-1893.
Canvas
Page 208
Publication
Boston,: Little, Brown and co.,
1867.
Subject terms
Classical dictionaries
Biography -- Dictionaries.
Greece -- Biography.
Rome -- Biography.

Technical Details

Link to this Item
https://name.umdl.umich.edu/acl3129.0001.001
Link to this scan
https://quod.lib.umich.edu/m/moa/acl3129.0001.001/223

Rights and Permissions

These pages may be freely searched and displayed. Permission must be received for subsequent distribution in print or electronically. Please go to http://www.umdl.umich.edu/ for more information.

Manifest
https://quod.lib.umich.edu/cgi/t/text/api/manifest/moa:acl3129.0001.001

Cite this Item

Full citation
"A Dictionary of Greek and Roman biography and mythology. By various writers. Ed. by William Smith. Illustrated by numerous engravings on wood." In the digital collection Making of America Books. https://name.umdl.umich.edu/acl3129.0001.001. University of Michigan Library Digital Collections. Accessed June 12, 2025.
Do you have questions about this content? Need to report a problem? Please contact us.